The present application is a 35 U.S.C. §371 national phase application based on PCT/EP2012/062815, filed Jul. 2, 2012, which claims priority of German Patent Application No. 10 2011 079 034.9, filed Jul. 12, 2011, the contents of both of which are incorporated in full by reference herein.
The invention relates to a method and an apparatus for actuating a technical system.
Model-based information interpretation (and the application thereof within the framework of model-based diagnosis) is becoming increasingly important. In this context, model-based methods have the advantage of an explicit and comprehensible description of the domain (e.g. of the technical system requiring a diagnosis). Such an explicit model can be examined and understood, which promotes acceptance by the user, particularly in respect of a diagnosis or an interpretation result. In addition, the models can be customized for new machines, extended by new domain knowledge and, depending on the type of presentation, even checked for correctness with reasonable effort. It is also possible to use a vocabulary of the model for man-machine interaction and hence for implementing an interactive interpretation process.
In the case of a logic-based representation of the domain model, the interpretation process is frequently implemented by means of what is known as (logic-based) abduction. This is an attempt to explain the observed information (such as sensor measurements and results from preprocessing processes) by using a formal model. In this context, allowance is made for the fact that the set of observations (e.g. owing to measurement inaccuracies, absence of sensors, etc.) is often incomplete by being able to assume missing information during an explanatory process. In formal terms, the object is thus to determine, for a given model T (also called the “theory”) and a set of observations O, a set A of assumptions (usually as a subset A⊂A from all possible assumptions A) such that the observations O are explained by the model T and also the assumptions A⊂A. In this case, the problem is worded as an optimization problem, i.e. the “best” such set A⊂A of assumptions is sought (according to the optimality criterion, e.g. the smallest set, or the set with the lowest weight).
In the practice of automatic information interpretation and/or diagnosis, there is—besides the problem of missing observations—also the problem that observations exist that cannot be explained with the given model. Typical causes of this are, by way of example, faulty sensors that deliver measured values outside an envisaged range, or else incomplete models that do not take account of at least one arising combination of observations. Such problems clearly restrict the practical usability of abduction-based information interpretation.
The object of the invention is to avoid the disadvantages cited above and to allow an opportunity for abduction even in the case of erroneous observations.
The object is achieved by proposing a method for actuating a technical system,
In this context, it should be noted that the actuation may relate to or comprise control, diagnosis or other processing of data from the technical system. In particular, the actuation in this case also comprises diagnosis, for example pertaining to the use of the information during a maintenance interval.
As a result of the wording as a multicriterion optimization problem, there is no longer the need to offset assumptions made and observations explained against one another.
The presented approach is highly generic, i.e. it does not require any assumptions about the preference relations used besides the intuitive stipulation that the addition of a further assumption (in the case of an unaltered observation set) cannot improve the preference and the addition of an explained observation (in the case of an unaltered assumption set) cannot impair the preference.
On account of the formal soundness of the approach, it is possible for particular properties of the result set (such as correctness, completeness, etc.) to be checked and substantiated, which is advantageous particularly in safety-critical applications.
Using the choice of underlying representational language and of preference relations, it is possible for the complexity of the problem solving process to be influenced and thus customized to any domain requirements.
One development is that two orders of preference over a subset of the observations and a subset of the assumptions are taken as a basis for determining tuples, so that the theory together with the subset of the assumptions explains the subset of the observations.
This formalizes the intuitive approach of explaining the largest possible portion of observations seen with as few assumptions as possible; in this case, optimality corresponds to pareto-optimality for the two orders of preference (since maximization of the observations and minimization of the assumptions are opposite or different aims). A solution to the problem consists of pareto-optimal pairs (A,O).
The general definition—based on general orders—of the optimality allows the use of various optimality terms, for example minimum and/or maximum number of elements, subset and/or superset relationship, or minimum and/or maximum sum of the weights of the elements contained.
Another development is that the relaxed abduction problem is determined to be RAP=(T,A,O,≦A,≦O),
wherein
In this case, the order ≦ is based on the orders ≦A and ≦O as follows:
(A,O)≃(A′,O′)A≃AA′O≃OO′
(A,O)<(A′,O′)(A≦AA′O<OO′)(A<AA′O≦OO′)
(A,O)≦(A′,O′)((A,O)<(A′,O′))((A,O)≃(A′,O′))
Hence, it is proposed that incorrect and missing information are two complementary facets of defective information and are therefore handled in the same way. In addition to the prerequisite that a required piece of information is based on a set of the assumptions A (also referred to as: abducibles or abducible axioms), the relaxed abduction ignores observations from the set O during production of hypotheses if required.
Accordingly, a good solution has a high level of significance for the observations while being based on assumptions as little as possible. Therefore, advantageously, the order ≦A is chosen to be monotone and the order ≦O is chosen to be anti-monotone for subset relationships.
In particular, it is a development that the relaxed abduction problem is solved by transforming the relaxed abduction problem into a hypergraph, so that tuples (A,O) are encoded by pareto-optimal paths in the hypergraph.
It is also a development that the pareto-optimal paths are determined by means of a label approach.
In addition, it is a development that hyperedges of the hypergraph are induced by transcriptions of prescribed rules.
A subsequent development is that the prescribed rules are determined as follows:
One embodiment is that a weighted hypergraph HRAP=(V,E) that is induced by the relaxed abduction problem is determined by
V={(AB),(A∃r.B)|A,BεNCT,rεNR},
wherein
VT={(AA),(AT)|AεNCT}⊂V
denotes a set of final states and E denotes a set of the hyperedges
e=(T(e),h(e),w(e)),
so that the following holds: there is an axiom aεT∪A| that justifies the derivation h(e)εV from T(e)⊂V on the basis of one of the prescribed rules, wherein the edge weight w(e) is determined according to
An alternative embodiment is that pX,t=(VX,t,EX,t) is determined as a hyperpath in H=(V,E) from X to t if
In this case, pX,y
V⊃VX,t={t}∪∪y
E⊃EX,t={e}∪∪y
A subsequent embodiment is that shortest hyperpaths are determined by taking account of two preferences.
It is also an embodiment that the shortest hyperpaths are determined by taking account of two preferences by means of a label correction algorithm.
One development is that the labels encode pareto-optimal paths to the hitherto found nodes of the hypergraph.
An additional embodiment is that alterations along the hyperedges are propagated by means of a meet operator and/or by means of a join operator.
Another embodiment is that the relaxed abduction problem is determined by means of a piece of description logic.
The above object is also achieved by means of an apparatus for actuating a technical system comprising a processing unit that is set up such that
The processing unit may, in particular, be a processor unit and/or an at least partially hardwired or logic circuit arrangement that, by way of example, is set up such that the method as described herein can be carried out. Said processing unit may be or comprise any type of processor or computer having correspondingly necessary peripherals (memory, input/output interfaces, input/output devices, etc).
The explanations above relating to the method apply to the apparatus accordingly. The apparatus may be embodied in one component or in distributed fashion in a plurality of components. In particular, it is also possible for a portion of the apparatus to be linked via a network interface (e.g. the Internet).
In addition, the object is achieved by proposing a system or a computer network comprising at least one of the apparatuses described here.
The solution presented herein also comprises a computer program product that can be loaded directly into a memory of a digital computer, comprising program code portions that are suitable for carrying out steps of the method described herein.
In addition, the aforementioned problem is solved by means of a computer-readable storage medium, e.g. an arbitrary memory, comprising instructions (e.g. in the form of program code) that can be executed by a computer and that are suited to the computer carrying out steps of the method described here.
The properties, features and advantages of this invention that are described above and also the manner in which they are achieved will become clearer and more distinctly comprehensible in connection with the schematic description of exemplary embodiments that follows, these being explained in more detail in connection with the drawings. In this case, elements that are the same or that have the same action may be provided with the same reference symbols for the sake of clarity.
The solution proposed here comprises particularly the following steps:
Taken together, these two steps allow solutions to an interpretation problem to be found even when it is not possible to explain all observations.
Overall, the field of application of model-based information interpretation (and hence also of model-based diagnosis) is significantly extended by the approach proposed here, since it is now also possible to process situations with an abundance of observation data (or a defectively formulated model). In this case, the demonstrated solution is conservative, i.e. in cases in which a conventional method delivers a solution, a corresponding solution is also provided by the approach proposed here.
Relaxed abduction with a solution is described in detail below.
Although abductive reasoning over principles of description logic knowledge is applied successfully to various information interpretation processes, it cannot provide adequate (or even any) results if it is confronted by incorrect information or incomplete models. The relaxed abduction proposed here solves this problem by ignoring incorrect information, for example. This can be done automatically on the basis of joint optimization of the sets of explained observations and required assumptions. By way of example, a method is presented that solves the relaxed abduction over εζ+ TBoxes based on the notion of shortest hyperpaths with multiple criteria.
Abduction was introduced in the late 19th century by Charles Sanders Pierce as an inference scheme aimed at deriving potential explanations for a particular observation. The rule formulated in this context
can be understood as an inversion of the modus ponens rule that allows φ to be derived as a hypothetical explanation for the occurrence of ω, under the assumption that the presence of φ in some sense justifies ω.
This general formulation cannot presuppose any causality between φ and ω in this case. Various notions of how φ justifies the presence of ω give rise to different notions of abductive inference, such as what is known as a set-cover-based approach, logic-based approaches or a knowledge-level approach.
In particular, the present case deals with logic-based abduction over εζ+ TBoxes. Correspondingly, other logic-based presentation schemes are also possible.
On account of its hypothetical nature, an abduction problem does not have a single solution but rather has a collection of alternative answers A1 . . . A2, . . . Ak, from among which optimal solutions are selected by means of an order of preference “<”. The expression
Ai≦Aj
denotes that Ai is “not worse” that “Aj”, with an indifference
Ai≦AjAj≦Ai, where Ai≃Aj
and a strict preference
Ai≦AjAj≃Ai where Ai<Aj
being determined. It is then possible for a (normal) preference-based abduction problem to be defined as follows:
Definition 1: Preference-Based Abduction Problem
PAP=(T,A,O,≦A)
Typical orders of preference over sets are or comprise
The first two orders of preference give preference to a set A over any of its subsets; this monotonicity property is formalized in definition 2 below.
Definition 2: monotone and anti-monotone order
Applications of abductive information interpretation using a formal domain model include media interpretation and diagnostics for complex technical systems such as production machines. These domains have many, in some cases simple, observations on account of a large number of sensors, whereas the model for all of these observations is often inadequately or incompletely specified. The following example illustrates how the classical definition of abduction can fail in a specific situation:
A production system comprises a diagnosis unit, wherein the production system has been mapped using a model. The model indicates that a fluctuating supply of current is manifested by intermittent failures in a main control unit, while the communication links remain operational and a mechanical gripper in the production system is unaffected (the observations are deemed to be modeled as a causal consequence of the diagnosis).
It is now assumed that a new additional vibration sensor observes low-frequency vibrations in the system. If the diagnostic model has not yet been extended in respect of this vibration sensor, which means that the observations of the vibration sensor also cannot be taken into account, the low-frequency vibrations delivered by the vibration sensor will unsettle the diagnostic process and prevent effective diagnosis in relation to the supply of current, even though the data delivered by the vibration sensor could actually be totally irrelevant.
Hence, the extension of the system by the vibration sensor results in the diagnosis no longer working reliably.
This flaw is based—according to the above definition of the preferred abduction problem—on the need for an admissible solution to have to explain every single observation oiεO|. This severely restricts the practical applicability of logic-based abduction to real industry applications in which an ever greater number of sensor data items produce and provide information that is not (yet) taken into account by the model.
An extension of logic-based abduction is therefore proposed below, so that even a wealth of data provide the desired results, e.g. diagnoses, flexibly and correctly.
Relaxed Abduction
Whereas, for simple models, it is still possible for incorrect information to be identified and possibly removed in a preprocessing step with a reasonable amount of effort, this is not possible for many real and correspondingly complex models, also because the relevance of a piece of information is dependent on the interpretation thereof and hence is not known in advance.
Hence, it is proposed that incorrect and missing information are two complementary facets of defective information and are therefore handled in the same way. In addition to the prerequisite that a required piece of information is based on the set of the assumptions A (also referred to as: abducibles or abducible axioms), the relaxed abduction ignores observations from the set O during production of hypotheses if required. This is formalized in definition 3.
Definition 3: Relaxed Abduction Problem
RAP=(T,A,O,≦A,≦O)
Accordingly, a good solution has a high level of significance for the observations while being based on assumptions as little as possible. Therefore, advantageously, the order ≦A is chosen to be monotone and the order ≦O is chosen to be anti-monotone for subset relationships.
Using inclusion as an order criterion over sets, the following will hold:
A≦AA′A⊂A′ and
O≦OO′O⊃O′.
For the example cited above with the augmented vibration sensor, a minimal solution that explains all observations apart from the vibrations is obtained on the basis of the order. Therefore, this vibration is not taken into account in the diagnosis, which allows the fluctuating supply of current to be indicated as the result of the diagnosis.
Assertion 1: Conservativeness:
Evidence:
Conservativeness states that under ordinary circumstances relaxed abduction provides all solutions (provided that there are some) to the corresponding standard abduction problem (i.e. the nonrelaxed abduction problem). Since the ≦A-order and the ≦O-order are typically competing optimization aims, it is expedient to treat relaxed abduction as an optimization problem with two criteria. ≦-Minimal solutions then correspond to pareto-optimal points in the space of all combinations (A,O) that meet the logical requirements of a solution (consistency and explanation of the observations).
Assertion 2: Pareto-Optimality of RAP:
Evidence:
The next section provides an approach in order to solve a relaxed abduction. This approach is based on the simultaneous optimization of ≦A and ≦O.
Solving Relaxed Abduction
The description logic εζ+ is a member of the εζ family, for which a subsumption can be verified in PTIME. εζ+ concept descriptions are defined by
C::=T|A|CC|∃r.C
(where AεNC is a concept name and rεNR is a role name). εζ+ axioms are
Since any εζ+ TBox can be normalized with only a linear increase in magnitude, it holds that all axioms have one of the following (normal) forms:
for A1, A2, BεNCT=NC∪{T} and r1, r2, sεNR.
Accordingly, (NF1) describes a concept inclusion “all objects in a class A1 are also objects in a class B”. (NF2) describes: “if an object belongs to class A1 and to class A2 then it also belongs to class B”. This can be shortened to “A1 and A2 are implied by B”. (NF3) denotes: “if an object belongs to class A1 then it is linked to at least one object in class B via a relation r”. Accordingly, (NF4) describes: “if an object is linked to at least one object in class A2 by means of a relation r then said object belongs to class B”. The normal forms (NF5) and (NF6) are obtained accordingly for the roles r1, r2, sεNR.
In addition to standard refutation-based table reasoning, the εζ family allows a completion-based reasoning scheme that explicitly derives valid subsumptions, specifically using a set of rules in the style of Gentzen's sequent calculus (also called “Gentzen calculus”).
The rules (completion rules CR and initialization rules IR) are presented below:
A graph structure which is produced using the rules allows subsumptions to be derived.
By way of example, it is assumed that both the set of assumptions A and the set of observations O, like the theory T, are axioms of the description logic.
The axiom-oriented representation allows a high level of flexibility and reuse of information.
From Completion Rules to Hypergraphs
Since the rules shown above are a complete evidence system for εζ+, any normalized axiom set can accordingly be mapped as a hypergraph (or as an appropriate representation of such a hypergraph), the nodes of which are axioms of type (NF1) and (NF3) over the concepts and the role names that are used in the axiom set (in line with all statements that are admissible as a premise or conclusion in a derivation step).
Hyperedges of the hypergraph are induced by transpositions of the rules (CR1) to (CR6); by way of example, an instantization of the rule (CR4), which derives CF from C∃r.D and DE using the axiom ∃r.EF, induces a hyperedge
{C∃r.D,DE}→CF.
This correspondence can also be extended to relaxed abduction problems as follows: Both T and A contain arbitrary εζ+ axioms in normal form that can justify individual derivation steps represented by a hyperedge (in order to simplify the representation, it can be assumed that A∩T=∅ holds).
Elements from the set of all observations O, on the other hand, represent information that is to be justified (i.e. that is derived), and therefore correspond to nodes of the hypergraph. This requires axioms from O to be only of type (NF1) and (NF3); this is a restriction that is usable in practice, since (NF2) axioms and (NF4) axioms can be converted into an (NF1) axiom, specifically using a new concept name, and since role inclusion axioms are not needed in order to express observations about domain objects. Preferably, the hyperedges are provided with a label on the basis of this criterion. This is also evident from the definition below.
Definition 4: Induced Hypergraphs HRAP:
In this context, it should be noted that the magnitude of HRAP is bounded polynomially in |NC| and |NR|. Checking whether a concept inclusion DE(C∃r.D) can be derived also checks whether the graph contains a hyperpath from VT to the node DE(C∃r.D).
Intuitively, there is a hyperpath from X to t if there is a hyperedge that connects a particular set of nodes Y to t, and each yiεY| can be reached from X via a hyperpath. This is formalized using the definition below.
Definition 5: Hyperpath:
This section provides an exemplary explanation of an algorithm for solving the relaxed abduction problem RAP. This involves determining the shortest hyperpaths by taking into account two different criteria (multi-aim optimization).
Thus, an extended label correction algorithm for finding shortest paths using two criteria in a graph is proposed on the basis of [Skriver, A. J. V.: A classification of bicriterion shortest path (bsp) algorithms. Asia-Pacific Journal of Operational Research 17, pages 199-212 (2000)]. Thus, the graph is presented in a compact form using two lists S and R (see also: Baader, F., Brandt, S., Lutz, C.: Pushing the EL envelope. In: Proceedings of the 19th International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence. Pages 364-369 (2005)). The entries in the list are extended by labels that encode the pareto-optimal paths to the previously found node. Alterations are propagated along the weighted edges using
In this case, the meet operator is defined as follows:
The join operator can be defined as follows:
In this context, it should be noted that the “remove_dominated” functionality removes those labels that code relatively poor paths.
When saturation has been reached, the labels of all <-| minimal paths in HRAP are collected in the set
MP(HRAP):=∪vεVlabel(v).
As already explained, the algorithm shown in
In line 7, all axioms a from T and A are selected in order and for each of these axioms a check is performed to determine whether the individual rules (CR1) to (CR6) apply. This is shown by way of example from line 8 onward for the rule (CR4). If need be, a new label L* is added in line 13 and a check is performed in line 14 to determine whether the label has been changed. If this is the case, the previous label entry is removed in line 15. Accordingly, the labels are added or updated.
In line 17, a check is performed to determine whether saturation has occurred, i.e. no further change is needed to be taken into account.
In this context, it should be noted that even though the order of propagations is irrelevant to correct ascertainment, it can have a significant effect on the number of candidates produced: finding almost optimal solutions may already result in a large number of less-than-optimal solutions in good time, which can be rejected. To improve performance, it is thus possible to use heuristics by first of all exhaustively applying propagations that are determined by elements of T and introducing assumptions only if such propagations are not possible.
Assertion 3: Correctness:
Evidence:
Since the node labels can grow exponentially with the magnitude A and O, it is worthwhile, for general orders of preference such as the set inclusion, considering the advantage of the present method in comparison with a brute force approach: iteration is performed over all pairs (A,O)εP(A)×P(O), and all tuples (A,O) are collected, so that T∪A|=O holds; finally, all ≦-dominant tuples are eliminated. This approach requires 2|A|+|O| deducibility tests, with each set that passes this test being tested for ≦-minimality. The solution presented is superior to a brute force approach in several respects:
Other selections for ≦A and ≦O| can lead to more considerable savings of computation effort, since the orders of preference are used as a pruning criterion while the solution is generated. This allows the present approach to be used for approximation.
If, by way of example, the assumption set and the observation set are compared not by means of set inclusion but rather by means of cardinality, the maximum label magnitude is decreased to |A|·|O|. This could—depending on the order of the rule application—not result in optimal solutions, however.
In a more complex design, e.g. for an installation or a technical system, it is possible to allocate numerical weights for observations and/or abducible axioms so that only such solutions as are substantially poorer than others are dropped. Alternatively, it is possible to use weights (or scores) in order to calculate limits for a maximum number of points that can be achieved by a partial solution; this number of points can be used as pruning criterion.
Hence, the present approach provides an opportunity for relaxed abduction for a description logic. Relaxed abduction extends logic-based abduction by the option of interpreting incorrect information for incomplete models. A solution to relaxed abduction over εζ+ knowledge bases is presented on the basis of pareto-optimal hyperpaths in the derivation graph. The performance of this approach also has critical advantages over that of mere enumeration despite the inherent exponential growth of node labels.
The proposed algorithm can accordingly be applied to other description logics for which it is possible to determine subsumption by means of completion. This is the case for the εζ++ description logic, for example.
The relaxed abduction described in the present case allows various specializations that are obtained from various selection options for ≦A and ≦O. By way of example, approximated solutions can be generated very efficiently (i.e. with a linear label magnitude) if set cardinality is used as a dominance criterion. It is also possible for the axioms to have weights allocated in order to allow early or even lossless pruning of less-than-optimum partial solutions; in this case, the label magnitudes are also reduced.
The technical system may be a technical installation, assembly, process monitoring, a power station or the like.
Although the invention has been illustrated and described in more detail using the at least one exemplary embodiment shown, the invention is not restricted thereto and other variations can be derived therefrom by a person skilled in the art without departing from the scope of protection of the invention.
Number | Date | Country | Kind |
---|---|---|---|
10 2011 079 034 | Jul 2011 | DE | national |
Filing Document | Filing Date | Country | Kind | 371c Date |
---|---|---|---|---|
PCT/EP2012/062815 | 7/2/2012 | WO | 00 | 1/13/2014 |
Publishing Document | Publishing Date | Country | Kind |
---|---|---|---|
WO2013/007547 | 1/17/2013 | WO | A |
Number | Name | Date | Kind |
---|---|---|---|
4656603 | Dunn | Apr 1987 | A |
4783741 | Mitterauer | Nov 1988 | A |
4813013 | Dunn | Mar 1989 | A |
5018075 | Ryan et al. | May 1991 | A |
5293323 | Doskocil et al. | Mar 1994 | A |
5631831 | Bird et al. | May 1997 | A |
5712960 | Chiopris et al. | Jan 1998 | A |
5802256 | Heckerman et al. | Sep 1998 | A |
5810747 | Brudny et al. | Sep 1998 | A |
5812994 | Imlah | Sep 1998 | A |
5852811 | Atkins | Dec 1998 | A |
5870701 | Wachtel | Feb 1999 | A |
5884294 | Kadar et al. | Mar 1999 | A |
6012152 | Douik et al. | Jan 2000 | A |
6044347 | Abella et al. | Mar 2000 | A |
6275817 | Reed et al. | Aug 2001 | B1 |
6278987 | Reed et al. | Aug 2001 | B1 |
6351675 | Tholen et al. | Feb 2002 | B1 |
6389406 | Reed et al. | May 2002 | B1 |
6394263 | McCrory | May 2002 | B1 |
6505184 | Reed et al. | Jan 2003 | B1 |
6529888 | Heckerman et al. | Mar 2003 | B1 |
6701516 | Li | Mar 2004 | B1 |
6745161 | Arnold et al. | Jun 2004 | B1 |
6782376 | Sato et al. | Aug 2004 | B2 |
6910003 | Arnold et al. | Jun 2005 | B1 |
7181376 | Fine et al. | Feb 2007 | B2 |
7313515 | Crouch et al. | Dec 2007 | B2 |
7313573 | Leung et al. | Dec 2007 | B2 |
7376556 | Bennett | May 2008 | B2 |
7389208 | Solinsky | Jun 2008 | B1 |
7392185 | Bennett | Jun 2008 | B2 |
7421738 | Harp et al. | Sep 2008 | B2 |
7450523 | Robertson et al. | Nov 2008 | B1 |
7555431 | Bennett | Jun 2009 | B2 |
7606784 | Mathias et al. | Oct 2009 | B2 |
7613667 | Coen et al. | Nov 2009 | B2 |
7624007 | Bennett | Nov 2009 | B2 |
7647225 | Bennett et al. | Jan 2010 | B2 |
7657424 | Bennett | Feb 2010 | B2 |
7672841 | Bennett | Mar 2010 | B2 |
7694226 | Covannon et al. | Apr 2010 | B2 |
7698131 | Bennett | Apr 2010 | B2 |
7702508 | Bennett | Apr 2010 | B2 |
7720787 | Pope et al. | May 2010 | B2 |
7725307 | Bennett | May 2010 | B2 |
7725320 | Bennett | May 2010 | B2 |
7725321 | Bennett | May 2010 | B2 |
7729904 | Bennett | Jun 2010 | B2 |
7730020 | Leung et al. | Jun 2010 | B2 |
7783582 | Doctor et al. | Aug 2010 | B2 |
7831426 | Bennett | Nov 2010 | B2 |
7836077 | Azvine et al. | Nov 2010 | B2 |
7873519 | Bennett | Jan 2011 | B2 |
7912702 | Bennett | Mar 2011 | B2 |
7962321 | de Kleer | Jun 2011 | B2 |
7975227 | Covannon et al. | Jul 2011 | B2 |
8010560 | Becker et al. | Aug 2011 | B2 |
8024610 | de Kleer | Sep 2011 | B2 |
8060567 | Carroll et al. | Nov 2011 | B2 |
8065319 | Ding et al. | Nov 2011 | B2 |
8078559 | Talbot et al. | Dec 2011 | B2 |
8170906 | Von Schweber et al. | May 2012 | B2 |
8229734 | Bennett | Jul 2012 | B2 |
8244821 | Carroll et al. | Aug 2012 | B2 |
8271257 | de Kleer | Sep 2012 | B2 |
8285438 | Mylaraswamy et al. | Oct 2012 | B2 |
8285664 | Ylonen | Oct 2012 | B2 |
8352277 | Bennett | Jan 2013 | B2 |
8375099 | Carroll et al. | Feb 2013 | B2 |
8375303 | Covannon et al. | Feb 2013 | B2 |
8458229 | Oliver et al. | Jun 2013 | B2 |
8463556 | Kaye | Jun 2013 | B2 |
8543565 | Feng | Sep 2013 | B2 |
8572290 | Mukhopadhyay et al. | Oct 2013 | B1 |
8607311 | Becker et al. | Dec 2013 | B2 |
8660849 | Gruber et al. | Feb 2014 | B2 |
8660974 | Ylonen | Feb 2014 | B2 |
8666923 | Ylonen | Mar 2014 | B2 |
8670979 | Gruber et al. | Mar 2014 | B2 |
8670985 | Lindahl et al. | Mar 2014 | B2 |
8676904 | Lindahl | Mar 2014 | B2 |
8677377 | Cheyer et al. | Mar 2014 | B2 |
8682649 | Bellegarda | Mar 2014 | B2 |
8682667 | Haughay | Mar 2014 | B2 |
8688446 | Yanagihara | Apr 2014 | B2 |
8706472 | Ramerth et al. | Apr 2014 | B2 |
8706503 | Cheyer et al. | Apr 2014 | B2 |
8712776 | Bellegarda et al. | Apr 2014 | B2 |
8713021 | Bellegarda | Apr 2014 | B2 |
8713119 | Lindahl | Apr 2014 | B2 |
8718047 | Vieri et al. | May 2014 | B2 |
8719005 | Lee et al. | May 2014 | B1 |
8719006 | Bellegarda | May 2014 | B2 |
8719014 | Wagner | May 2014 | B2 |
8731942 | Cheyer et al. | May 2014 | B2 |
8743708 | Robertson et al. | Jun 2014 | B1 |
8751238 | James et al. | Jun 2014 | B2 |
8762152 | Bennett et al. | Jun 2014 | B2 |
8762156 | Chen | Jun 2014 | B2 |
8762469 | Lindahl | Jun 2014 | B2 |
8768702 | Mason et al. | Jul 2014 | B2 |
8768869 | Rubin | Jul 2014 | B1 |
8775442 | Moore et al. | Jul 2014 | B2 |
8781836 | Foo et al. | Jul 2014 | B2 |
8799000 | Guzzoni et al. | Aug 2014 | B2 |
8812294 | Kalb et al. | Aug 2014 | B2 |
8825642 | Zatkin et al. | Sep 2014 | B2 |
8839344 | Becker et al. | Sep 2014 | B2 |
8862252 | Rottler et al. | Oct 2014 | B2 |
8892446 | Cheyer et al. | Nov 2014 | B2 |
8898568 | Bull et al. | Nov 2014 | B2 |
8903716 | Chen et al. | Dec 2014 | B2 |
8930191 | Gruber et al. | Jan 2015 | B2 |
8935167 | Bellegarda | Jan 2015 | B2 |
8942986 | Cheyer et al. | Jan 2015 | B2 |
8965818 | Zillner et al. | Feb 2015 | B2 |
8977255 | Freeman et al. | Mar 2015 | B2 |
8996340 | Cheriere et al. | Mar 2015 | B2 |
8996376 | Fleizach et al. | Mar 2015 | B2 |
9047565 | Willems et al. | Jun 2015 | B2 |
9053089 | Bellegarda | Jun 2015 | B2 |
9075783 | Wagner | Jul 2015 | B2 |
9076448 | Bennett et al. | Jul 2015 | B2 |
9092109 | Carroll et al. | Jul 2015 | B2 |
9117447 | Gruber et al. | Aug 2015 | B2 |
9153142 | Bagchi et al. | Oct 2015 | B2 |
9160738 | Becker | Oct 2015 | B2 |
9190062 | Haughay | Nov 2015 | B2 |
9190063 | Bennett et al. | Nov 2015 | B2 |
9213821 | Saxena et al. | Dec 2015 | B2 |
9240955 | Mukhopadhyay et al. | Jan 2016 | B1 |
9256713 | March et al. | Feb 2016 | B2 |
9258306 | Saxena et al. | Feb 2016 | B2 |
9262612 | Cheyer | Feb 2016 | B2 |
9262719 | Soon-Shiong | Feb 2016 | B2 |
20030028469 | Bergman et al. | Feb 2003 | A1 |
20030073939 | Taylor et al. | Apr 2003 | A1 |
20030078838 | Szmanda | Apr 2003 | A1 |
20040030556 | Bennett | Feb 2004 | A1 |
20040117189 | Bennett | Jun 2004 | A1 |
20040193572 | Leary | Sep 2004 | A1 |
20040236580 | Bennett | Nov 2004 | A1 |
20040249618 | Fine et al. | Dec 2004 | A1 |
20040249635 | Bennett | Dec 2004 | A1 |
20050060323 | Leung et al. | Mar 2005 | A1 |
20050080614 | Bennett | Apr 2005 | A1 |
20050086046 | Bennett | Apr 2005 | A1 |
20050086049 | Bennett | Apr 2005 | A1 |
20050086059 | Bennett | Apr 2005 | A1 |
20060112048 | Talbot et al. | May 2006 | A1 |
20060122834 | Bennett | Jun 2006 | A1 |
20060122876 | Von Schweber et al. | Jun 2006 | A1 |
20060235696 | Bennett | Oct 2006 | A1 |
20060256953 | Pulaski et al. | Nov 2006 | A1 |
20070005650 | Coen et al. | Jan 2007 | A1 |
20070061110 | Tafazoli et al. | Mar 2007 | A1 |
20070094209 | Steward et al. | Apr 2007 | A1 |
20070094216 | Mathias et al. | Apr 2007 | A1 |
20070288405 | Menich | Dec 2007 | A1 |
20070288418 | Pope | Dec 2007 | A1 |
20070288419 | Strassner | Dec 2007 | A1 |
20070288467 | Strassner et al. | Dec 2007 | A1 |
20070288795 | Leung et al. | Dec 2007 | A1 |
20080015891 | Lee | Jan 2008 | A1 |
20080052078 | Bennett | Feb 2008 | A1 |
20080059153 | Bennett | Mar 2008 | A1 |
20080071714 | Menich et al. | Mar 2008 | A1 |
20080109318 | Szmanda | May 2008 | A1 |
20080140657 | Azvine et al. | Jun 2008 | A1 |
20080215327 | Bennett | Sep 2008 | A1 |
20080222058 | Doctor et al. | Sep 2008 | A1 |
20080255845 | Bennett | Oct 2008 | A1 |
20080270336 | Talbot et al. | Oct 2008 | A1 |
20080294415 | de Kleer | Nov 2008 | A1 |
20080294578 | de Kleer | Nov 2008 | A1 |
20080300878 | Bennett | Dec 2008 | A1 |
20080306899 | Gregory et al. | Dec 2008 | A1 |
20090006320 | Ding et al. | Jan 2009 | A1 |
20090018802 | de Kleer | Jan 2009 | A1 |
20090018984 | Solinsky | Jan 2009 | A1 |
20090070311 | Feng | Mar 2009 | A1 |
20090157401 | Bennett | Jun 2009 | A1 |
20090164469 | Becker et al. | Jun 2009 | A1 |
20090165110 | Becker et al. | Jun 2009 | A1 |
20090193493 | Becker et al. | Jul 2009 | A1 |
20090222921 | Mukhopadhyay et al. | Sep 2009 | A1 |
20090327172 | Liu et al. | Dec 2009 | A1 |
20090328133 | Strassner et al. | Dec 2009 | A1 |
20100005081 | Bennett | Jan 2010 | A1 |
20100010872 | Drummond et al. | Jan 2010 | A1 |
20100083056 | Mills | Apr 2010 | A1 |
20100205649 | Becker et al. | Aug 2010 | A1 |
20100228540 | Bennett | Sep 2010 | A1 |
20100235341 | Bennett | Sep 2010 | A1 |
20110093463 | Oliver et al. | Apr 2011 | A1 |
20110106745 | Ylonen | May 2011 | A1 |
20110118905 | Mylaraswamy et al. | May 2011 | A1 |
20110153362 | Valin et al. | Jun 2011 | A1 |
20110218855 | Cao et al. | Sep 2011 | A1 |
20110231356 | Vaidyanathan et al. | Sep 2011 | A1 |
20110289039 | Ylonen | Nov 2011 | A1 |
20110289045 | Ylonen | Nov 2011 | A1 |
20110314075 | Boldyrev et al. | Dec 2011 | A1 |
20120072386 | Willems et al. | Mar 2012 | A1 |
20120101793 | Cheriere et al. | Apr 2012 | A1 |
20120143013 | Davis et al. | Jun 2012 | A1 |
20120158391 | Vaske et al. | Jun 2012 | A1 |
20120185330 | Kleinrock et al. | Jul 2012 | A1 |
20120185424 | Vaidyanathan et al. | Jul 2012 | A1 |
20120197653 | Short et al. | Aug 2012 | A1 |
20120197751 | Zatkin et al. | Aug 2012 | A1 |
20120197874 | Zatkin et al. | Aug 2012 | A1 |
20120203727 | Schweber et al. | Aug 2012 | A1 |
20120226650 | Witchey | Sep 2012 | A1 |
20120265531 | Bennett | Oct 2012 | A1 |
20120301864 | Bagchi et al. | Nov 2012 | A1 |
20130054506 | Hubauer et al. | Feb 2013 | A1 |
20130110573 | Pye et al. | May 2013 | A1 |
20130203038 | Kumar et al. | Aug 2013 | A1 |
20130204813 | Master et al. | Aug 2013 | A1 |
20130211841 | Ehsani et al. | Aug 2013 | A1 |
20130212065 | Rahnama | Aug 2013 | A1 |
20130212130 | Rahnama | Aug 2013 | A1 |
20130310653 | Zillner et al. | Nov 2013 | A1 |
20140129504 | Soon-Shiong | May 2014 | A1 |
20140129557 | Rahnama | May 2014 | A1 |
20140129693 | Rahnama | May 2014 | A1 |
20140149337 | Hubauer et al. | May 2014 | A1 |
20140195664 | Rahnama | Jul 2014 | A1 |
20140214460 | Rahnama | Jul 2014 | A1 |
20140223561 | Mitola | Aug 2014 | A1 |
20140249875 | Junker et al. | Sep 2014 | A1 |
20140270467 | Blemel et al. | Sep 2014 | A1 |
20140277755 | Grimm et al. | Sep 2014 | A1 |
20140358865 | Brummel et al. | Dec 2014 | A1 |
20150039648 | Mukherjee et al. | Feb 2015 | A1 |
20150046388 | Sheth et al. | Feb 2015 | A1 |
20150079556 | Laitinen | Mar 2015 | A1 |
20150096026 | Kolacinski et al. | Apr 2015 | A1 |
20150142465 | Vaske et al. | May 2015 | A1 |
20150154178 | Fang | Jun 2015 | A1 |
20150199607 | Fang | Jul 2015 | A1 |
20150254330 | Chan et al. | Sep 2015 | A1 |
20150261825 | Fischer et al. | Sep 2015 | A1 |
20150269639 | Mistriel | Sep 2015 | A1 |
20150310497 | Valin et al. | Oct 2015 | A1 |
Number | Date | Country |
---|---|---|
2 421 545 | Mar 2002 | CA |
1092151 | Sep 1994 | CN |
101299303 | Nov 2008 | CN |
101872345 | Oct 2010 | CN |
Entry |
---|
Pino-Perez et al. “Preferences and explanation”, Artificial Intelligence 149, 2003, pp. 1-30. |
Aliseda—LLera “Seeking Explanations Abduction in Logic Philosophy of Science and Artificial Intelligence”, Dissertation, 1997, (Chapter 2,) pp. 44. |
Jin et al. “Pareto-Based Multiobjective Machine Learning: An Overview and Case Studies”, IEEE SMC, vol. 38, No. 3, 2008, pp. 397-415. |
Chinese Office Action (with English language translation) issued in counterpart Chinese Application No. 201280044282.4 dated Jun. 30, 2015. |
Baader, Franz and Brandt, Sebastian and Lutz, Carsten: Pushing the EL Envelope. In: Proceedings of the 19th International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (IJCAI 2005). (Professional Book Center, 2005). pp. 364-369. Isbn: 0938075934. (http://www.ijcai.org/papers/0372.pdf). |
Skriver, A.J.V. : A classifcation of bicriterion shortest path (bsp) algorithms. Asia-Pacifc Journal of Operational Research 17, pp. 199-212 (2000). |
Lecue F. et al.; “Applying Abduction in Semantic Web Service Composition”; WEB SERVICES, 2007. ICWS 2007, IEEE, PI; pp. 94-101; ISBN: 978-0-7695-2924-0; XP031119904; 2007; Jul. 1, 2007. |
International Search Report dated Oct. 10, 2012 issued in corresponding International patent application No. PCT/EP2012/062815. |
Written Opinion dated Oct. 10, 2012 issued in corresponding International patent application No. PCT/EP2012/062815. |
Wang, Huaiqing, Stephen Liao, and Lejian Liao. “Modeling constraint-based negotiating agents” Decision Support Systems 33.2 (2002): 201-217. |
Dung, Phan Mink “Negations as Hypotheses: An Abductive Foundation for Logic Programming.” ICLP. 1991. |
Eco, Umberto. “The Sign of Three: Dupin, Holmes, Peirce Advances in.” (1983). |
Endriss, Ulrich, et al. “The CIFF proof procedure for abductive logic programming with constraints.” Logics in Artificial Intelligence. Springer Berlin Heidelberg, 2004. 31-43. |
Ramoni, Marco, et al. “An epistemological framework for medical knowledge-based systems.” Systems, Man and Cybemetics, IEEE Transactions on 22.6 (1992): 1361-1375. |
Greiner, Russell, Barbara A. Smith, and Ralph W. Wilkerson. “A correction to the algorithm in Reiter's theory of diagnosis.” Artificial Intelligence 41.1 (1989): 79-88. |
Hobbs, Jerry R. “Abduction in natural language understanding.” Handbook of pragmatics (2004): 724-741. |
Harman, Gilbert H. “The inference to the best explanation.” The Philosophical Review 74.1 (1965): 88-95. |
Pereira, Luís Moniz, Joaquim Nunes Aparício, and José Júlio Alferes. “Hypothetical Reasoning with Well Founded Semantics.” SCAI. 1991. |
Poole, David. “Representing Diagnostic Knowledge for Probabilistic Horn Abduction.” IJCAI. 1991. |
Kakas, Antonis C., Robert A. Kowalski, and Francesca Toni. “Abductive logic programming.” Journal of logic and computation 2.6 (1992): 719-770. |
McIllraith, Sheila. “Generating tests using abduction.” Proc. of KR 94 (1994): 449-460. |
Baader, Franz, et al. “Matching in description logics.” Journal of Logic and Computation 9.3 (1999): 411-447. |
Hubauer, Thomas M., Steffen Lamparter, and Michael Pirker. “Relaxed abduction: Robust information interpretation for Incomplete models.” 24th International Workshop on Description Logics. 2011. |
Poole, David. “Probabilistic Horn abduction and Bayesian networks.” Artificial intelligence 64.1 (1993): 81-129. |
Poole, David. “Normality and Faults in Logic-Based Diagnosis.” IJCAI. vol. 89. 1989. |
Dung, Phan Mink “Representing Actions in Logic Programming and Its Applications in Database Updates.” ICLP. vol. 93. 1993. |
Apt, Krzysztof R., and Marc Bezem. “Acyclic programs.” New generation computing 9.3-4 (1991): 335-363. |
Console, Luca, Daniele Theseider Dupré, and Pietro Torasso. “A Theory of Diagnosis for Incomplete Causal Models.” IJCAI. 1989. |
Pirri, Fiora, and Clara Pizzuti. “Explaining incompatibilities in data dictionary design through abduction.” Data & knowledge engineering 13.2 (1994): 101-139. |
Mayer, Marta Cialdea, and Fiora Pirri “First order abduction via tableau and sequent calculi.” Logic Journal of IGPL 1.1 (1993): 99-117. |
Bylander, Tom, et al. “The computational complexity of abduction.” Artificial intelligence 49.1 (1991): 25-60. |
Eshghi, Kaye. “A Tractable Class of Abduction Problems.” IJCAI. 1993. |
Inoue, Katsumi. “Hypothetical reasoning in logic programs.” The Journal of Logic Programming 18.3 (1994): 191-227. |
Lin, Fangzhen, and Jia-Huai You. “Abduction in logic programming: A new definition and an abductive procedure based on rewriting.” Artificial Intelligence 140.1 (2002): 175-205. |
Eiter, Thomas, Georg Gottlob, and Nicola Leone. “Semantics and complexity of abduction from default theories.” Artificial Intelligence 90.1 (1997): 177-223. |
Eiter, Thomas, Georg Gottlob, and Nicola Leone. “Abduction from logic programs: Semantics and complexity.” Theoretical computer science 189.1 (1997): 129-177. |
Denecker, Marc, and Danny De Schreye. “SLDNFA: an abductive procedure for abductive logic programs.” The journal of logic programming 34.2 (1998): 111-167. |
Sakama, Chiaki, and Katsumi Inoue. “Abductive logic programming and disjunctive logic programming: their relationship and transferability.” The Journal of Logic Programming 44.1 (2000): 75-100. |
Kakas, Antonis C., Antonia Michael, and Costas Mourlas. “ACLP: Abductive constraint logic programming.” The Journal of Logic Programming 44.1 (2000): 129-177. |
Poole, David. “Logic Programming, Abduction and Probability.” FGCS. 1992. |
Noia, Tommaso Di, et al. “A system for principled matchmaking in an electronic marketplace.” International Journal of Electronic Commerce 8.4 (2004): 9-37. |
Di Noia, Tommaso, et al. “Abductive matchmaking using description logics.” IJCAI. vol. 3. 2003. |
McIlraith, Sheila A. “Logic-based abductive inference.” Knowledge Systems Laboratory, Technical Report KSL-98-19 (1998). |
Denecker, Marc, and Danny De Schreye. “Representing incomplete knowledge in abductive logic programming.” Journal of Logic and Computation 5.5 (1995): 553-577. |
Sakama, Chiaki, and Katsumi Inoue. “On the Equivalence between Disjunctive and Abductive Logic Programs.” ICLP. 1994. |
McIlraith, Sheila, and Raymond Reiter. “On tests for hypothetical reasoning.” Readings in model-based diagnosis (1992): 89-96. |
Eiter, Thomas, and Georg Gottlob. “The complexity of logic-based abduction.” Journal of the ACM (JACM) 42.1 (1995): 3-42. |
Kowalski, Robert A., Francesca Toni, and Gerhard Wetzel. “Executing suspended logic programs.” Fundamenta Informaticae 34.3 (1998): 203-224. |
Inoue, Katsumi, and Chiaki Sakama. “Abductive Framework for Nonmonotonic Theory Change.” IJCAI. vol. 95. 1995. |
Paul, Gabriele. “Approaches to abductive reasoning: an overview.” Artificial intelligence review 7.2 (1993): 109-152. |
Poole, David. “Representing diagnosis knowledge.” Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence 11.1-4 (1994): 33-50. |
Poole, David. “Logic programming, abduction and probability.” New Generation Computing 11.3-4 (1993): 377-400. |
Kakas, Antonis C., Robert A. Kowalski, and Francesca Toni. “The role of abduction in logic programming.” Handbook of logic in artificial intelligence and logic programming 5 (1998): 235-324. |
Colucci, Simona, et al. “Concept abduction and contraction for semantic-based discovery of matches and negotiation spaces in an e-marketplace.” Electronic Commerce Research and Applications 4.4 (2006): 345-361. |
Pople, Harry E. “On the Mechanization of Abductive Logic.” IJCAI. vol. 73. 1973. |
Denecker, Marc, and Antonis Kakas. “Abduction in logic programming.” Computational logic: Logic programming and beyond. Springer Berlin Heidelberg, 2002. 402-436. |
Van Nuffelen, Bert. “A-System: Problem solving through abduction.” BNAIC'01 Sponsors 1 (2001): 591-596. |
Bodlaender, et al. “On the MPA Problem in Probabilistic Networks.” BNAIC'01 Sponsors 1 (2001): 71-78. |
Hirata, Kouichi. “A classification of abduction: abduction for logic programming.” Machine intelligence 14. 1993. |
Denecker, Marc, Lode Missiaen, and Maurice Bruynooghe. “Temporal Reasoning with Abductive Event Calculus.” ECAI. 1992. |
Poole, David. “A logical framework for default reasoning.” Artificial intelligence 36.1 (1988): 27-47. |
Charniak, Eugene. Introduction to artificial intelligence. Pearson Education India, 1985. |
Eiter, Thomas, and Kazuhisa Makino. “On computing all abductive explanations.” AAAI/IAAI. 2002. |
Josephson, John R., and Susan G. Josephson. Abductive inference: Computation, philosophy, technology. Cambridge University Press, 1996. |
Magnani, Lorenzo. “Abductive reasoning: philosophical and educational perspectives in medicine.” Advanced models of cognition for medical training and practice. Springer Berlin Heidelberg, 1992. 21-41. |
Eshghi, Kave. “Abductive Planning with Event Calculus.” ICLP/SLP. 1988. |
Ng, Hwee Tou, and Raymond J. Mooney. “On the Role of Coherence in Abductive Explanation3.” (1990). |
Gentner, Dedre. “Analogical inference and analogical access.” Analogica (1988): 63-88. |
Hobbs, Jerry R., et al. “Interpretation as abduction.” Proceedings of the 26th annual meeting on Association for Computational Linguistics. Association for Computational Linguistics, 1988. |
Stickel, Mark E. “A Prolog-like inference system for computing minimum-cost abductive explanations in natural-language interpretation.” Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence 4.1-2 (1991): 89-105. |
Poole, David. “Explanation and prediction: an architecture for default and abductive reasoning.” Computational Intelligence 5.2 (1989): 97-110. |
Veit, Daniel, et al. “Matchmaking for autonomous agents in electronic marketplaces.” Proceedings of the fifth International conference on Autonomous agents. ACM, 2001. |
Christiansen, Henning, and Veronica Dahl. “HYPROLOG: A new logic programming language with assumptions and abduction.” Logic Programming. Springer Berlin Heidelberg, 2005. 159-173. |
Cal Andrea, et al. “A description logic based approach for matching user profiles.” 2004 International Workshop on Description Logics. 2004. |
McIlraith, Sheila, and Ray Reiter. “On experiments for hypothetical reasoning.” Proc. 2nd International Workshop on Principles of Diagnosis. 1992. |
Poole, David. “A methodology for using a default and abductive reasoning system.” International Journal of Intelligent Systems 5.5 (1990): 521-548. |
Number | Date | Country | |
---|---|---|---|
20140149337 A1 | May 2014 | US |